- Law of Identity - an object is the same as itself:
A ⇔ A - Law of Noncontradiction - contradictory statements cannot both at the same time be true, e.g. the two propositions "A is B" and "A is not B" are mutually exclusive:
¬(A ∧ ¬A) - Law of the Excluded Middle - Everything (that is, every proposition) must either be true or not true. There is no in-between:
A ∨ ¬A
¬(P ∧ Q) ⇔ ¬P ∨ ¬Q
If we let P = A, and Q = ¬A, then
¬(A ∧ ¬A) ⇔ ¬A ∨ ¬¬A,
which is the same as:
¬(A ∧ ¬A) ⇔ ¬A ∨ A
The left hand side is the Law of Noncontradiction, and the right hand side is the Law of the Excluded Middle.
These are self-evident logical principles - fundamental axioms that cannot be proved (or disproved), but must be accepted (or rejected) a priori. In other words, there is nothing "under" them - they cannot be decomposed into more basic principles. They are similar, conceptually, to the axioms in Euclidean Geometry (e.g. the famous "Parallel Postulate"). Other types of geometry are possible, but if you begin with certain postulates you get Euclidean geometry. Other postulates generate other geometries. In logic, other postulates could be substituted for the Laws of Thought, and in fact have been in other traditions such as Buddhism, which celebrates contradiction. Paraconsistent logic (a type of logic that deals with contradictions differently than classical logic) does not depend on the Law of Noncontradiction. Even Greek philosophy before Aristotle (and Parmenides, who proposed similar laws) did not always embrace these concepts. But practically everything we know of traditional Western Philosophy and Logic embodies these principles. Preceding Aristotle by over a century, Heraclitus believed that contradictions were necessary - that their existence was essential to a thing's identity:
- "Not only could it be stated that identity is the strife of oppositions but that there could be no identity without such strife within the entity."
- "Cold things grow warm; warm grows cold; wet grows dry; parched grows moist."
This development in logic admirably suited the predispositions of the Western mind, and certainly helped shape it. Western philosophy to a very large extent has been founded upon the Laws of Thought and similar ground rules. We believe that our thinking should strive to eliminate ideas that are vague, contradictory, or ambiguous, and the best way to accomplish this, and thereby ground our thinking in clear and distinct ideas, is to strictly follow laws of thought.
But are these laws simply axioms, or can the be proved? It doesn't appear that there is a direct proof, but to some degree they must be accepted a priori. However, Aristotle pointed out attempts to logically justify these axioms were unnecessary. He held that the axioms of classical logic are self evident because 1) all syllogisms rely on them, and 2) because they can be defended through retortion.
A defense through retortion occurs whenever an argument must rely upon the very principle it seeks to challenge or overturn. Any attempt to form a syllogism to refute the Laws of Thought will have to rely on the very axioms it seeks to overturn, leading to an implicit reliance on the axioms, which is a self refutation (i.e., the "Stolen Concept fallacy"). In other words, it is impossible for the laws of logic to not be correct. If I were to say, "the Law of Non-Contradiction is false", this presupposes the Law of Non-Contradiction itself, because I am simultaneously intending to convey, "It is not true that the Law of Identity is true".
In spite of how dominant these laws of thought have been, they have not been without their critics, and philosophers from Heraclitus to Hegel have leveled powerful arguments against them. But the issue does not seem to be whether the laws are applicable or not, but where and when are they applicable. Certainly, the laws of thought have a place, but what is that place? As Walt Whitman wrote in “Song of Myself”:
- "Do I contradict myself?
Very well, then, I contradict myself.
(I am large, I contain multitudes.)"
- "Everything is real and not real.
Both real and not real.
Neither real nor not real.
That is Lord Buddha's teaching."
- "what can be said at all can be said clearly, and what we cannot talk about we must pass over in silence"
The Persian philosopher, Avicenna (also known as Ibn Sina) has a famous quote about how to deal with those who disregard the Law of Noncontradiction:
- "Anyone who denies the Law of Noncontradiction should be beaten and burned until he admits that to be beaten is not the same as not to be beaten, and to be burned is not the same as not to be burned."
Philosophical naturalists and realists attempt to understand the world using a reason and evidence-based approach. They employ logic and empiricism, filtered through external review and correction, iterative refinement, and ultimately balanced by informed judgment which also has to take unknowns and risk into account. Experience has shown this to bear the greatest fruit if the goal is truly to understand the world.
Those who approach these questions from a religious or mystical point of view, will achieve an outcome which embodies whatever results they feel are enlightening, thrilling, comforting, uplifting, or that allow them to persist in their irrational (by definition) and incoherent (i.e., disorganized and internally inconsistent) mystically-based world view. To allow the introduction of multiple, inconsistent concepts during an exchange causes confusion because of the impreciseness (and even trickery) of language. The epistemologies feeding our different world views (science/evidence/reason/naturalism vs mystical/religious/irrational/revelatory) differ. The irrational approach is based on revelation/inspiration/emotion/myth/sacred texts, and the scientific world view is based on observation/experiment/measurement/evidence/theory/methodology/coherence/critique. It is difficult, probably impossible, to bridge the gap between these diametrically opposite positions.
However, the irrational does have its place in our world. Humans are not robots, but are primarily emotional beings with a veneer of rationality laid on top. Not everything is best dealt with through a reductionist, rational approach. We would lead a very narrow existence, indeed, as well as barren and joyless, to try to apply these or similar laws to every human experience. Of what use is it to be entirely reason-based when enjoying the beauty of nature, the joy of your pet, or the laughter of friends and relatives. However, in the focused realm of science, whose goal is merely to explain how things work and of what they are made, this type of restricted and disciplined thought is a perfect fit.
No comments:
Post a Comment